Home Page

Just a site for me to get the hang of putting together web pages.  Not sure what sort of content I’ll end up with.  I’ve put my undergraduate dissertation on Kant on here as an experiment  - feel free to have a look.

Contact: mk430@hotmail.com

 

 

Kant and the Subjectivity of Nature:

An examination of some aspects of Strawson’s attack on transcendental idealism

 

 

Contents

Introduction                             

Strawson's Critique                  

Kant as Phenomenalist

Kant as Noumenalist                

Conclusion                              

Bibliography                            

 

 

Introduction

 

  The purpose of this dissertation is to critically assess some aspects of P.F. Strawson's attack on transcendental idealism as it occurs in his commentary on Kant's 'Critique of Pure Reason', 'The Bounds of Sense'.  The general question at issue is whether or not one need accept Strawson's dismissive attitude and settle for the 'austere' reconstruction of Kant's text (or rather parts of that text) that he offers.  Thus, what follows is a response to a position which Strawson summarizes in his introductory chapter :

The doctrines of transcendental idealism, and the associated picture of the receiving and ordering apparatus of the mind producing Nature as we know it out of the unknowable reality of things as they are in themselves, are undoubtedly the chief obstacles to a sympathetic understanding of the Critique. (p.22)

The reason for such an indirect approach to Kant's text is primarily the importance and influence of Strawson's work which stands as an unavoidable hurdle for anyone wishing to offer a sympathetic reading of transcendental idealism.  If evidence were needed for this, then it could be gathered by simply making a survey of how many books and articles begin with a quote from Strawson's work or at least state their position as regards that work in their opening pages (e.g. P. Kitcher, H.E. Allison, T.E. Wilkerson, K. Davies, R.C.S. Walker....).

 

  Strawson's work is best understood as a recent and especially eloquent product of a particular brand of Kantian scholarship, one whose position as orthodoxy disguises its radical nature (as P.Kitcher notes, p.3).  Whilst no attempt will be made here to fully discuss the numerous divergent strands of Kantian criticism, two distinct traditions will be briefly considered in order to raise certain questions of interpretation which cannot be fully treated within the body of this dissertation and also to place Strawson's work within its context.  The first approach, to which Strawson most decidedly does not belong, may be roughly characterized as that which consists in the interpretation and development of Kantian doctrines within the continental (especially German) speculative philosophical tradition running from immediate successors to Kant who disputed over his legacy (Hegel, Schopenhauer, etc.) through to the recent resurgence of interest in Kant amongst postmodernist thinkers.  One interesting question of interpretation which arises out of any consideration of this tradition is the extent to which it is possible to examine the doctrines of the first Critique out of the context of the critical philosophy as a whole.  Thus, for instance, of such matters R.C. Solomon writes, "The third Critique, 'The Critique of Judgement', has been considered the least consequential of the three, and is often neglected in English Kantian scholarship; but this is certainly not true on the continent, where Kant's influence was based at least as much on this work as upon the other two" (p.27).  An extreme example of such unfamiliar emphasis is the above mentioned postmodernist interest in Kant.  This has taken the form, in some cases, of such weight being given to the third Critique and especially to the doctrines concerning the Sublime that the whole of the critical philosophy is seen, as it were, through a fantastically distorting lens whereby Kant is seen to radically undermine the epistemological and moral conclusions of the earlier critical works, a far cry from the view of Kant as Enlightenment champion of reason; rather Kant as Romantic irrationalist.

 

  An example of the neglectful tendency noted by Solomon amongst English Language Kantians is to be found in Kitcher's 'Kant's Transcendental Psychology'.  She complains that Strawson's knife-wielding approach leaves us little to read, making a case for a sympathetic reading of the doctrines of transcendental psychology on the grounds that it would allow a much clearer understanding of key parts of the first Critique.  The closing sentence of her book reads, "The great book is more rewarding - and makes much better sense - when it is read intact" (p.230).  It is surely fair to ask whether or not it is also the case that "the great book" would be even more rewarding and make even better (if radically different) sense if it were to be read in the context of a system wherein it serves a purpose which is arguably preliminary.  A particularly interesting line of post-Kantian development is that via Hegel into objective idealism which raises questions concerning Kant's neglect of the influence of society on conceptual frameworks (raising the spectre of cultural relativism as against his universalizing pretensions) and the connected accusation of over-emphasising the individual.  These questions comprise, in a sense, the other side to the coin of Strawson's complaint of Kant's "transcendental subjectivism" (p.22).

 

  These issues cannot be dealt with further here in that they fall well outside the scope of the questions under consideration.  They are raised in order to illustrate that one may question Strawson's approach (and indeed the approach of much English language Kantian scholarship, whether for or against transcendental idealism) from a position very different from that which is adopted here.

 

  The other interpretative approach to be considered here might loosely be called the logical strand and it is here that Strawson belongs, with those who reject the speculative tradition and also that which they find in Kant that strikes them as metaphysical or psychological.  It is not suprising that such an approach should predominate in Britain (though not only here) where, it might be held, the afterglow of Logical Positivism lingers on, beyond redemption, yet still exerting an influence.  Indeed Ayer in 'Language, Truth and Logic', the key text of British Logical Positivism, bemoans the fact that Kant "made the impossibility of a transcendent metaphysic not, as we do, a matter of logic, but a matter of fact" (p.46f.).  It is also interesting to note that, when shaking their heads over Kant's failings, both Strawson and Ayer refer to the Wittgensteinian point that "in order to be able to draw a limit to thought, we should have to be able to find both sides of the limit thinkable" (TLP, preface, p.3; cf.Strawson, p.44 and Ayer, p.47).  However, as we shall see, an interpretation of Wittgenstein's talk of 'limits' is possible which sheds an interesting and not unsympathetic light on certain aspects of transcendental idealism.  A further positivistic connection, which should be mentioned here as it cannot be dealt with more fully, concerns the fact that Strawson ascribes a "principle of significance" to Kant that bears a striking resemblance to the verification principle.  The point which must be made here is that such an ascription is highly questionable given Kant's views on the statements with which practical reason is concerned (see p.19f.).

 

  Walker acknowledges the importance of Strawson, noting that he "can be taken as the representative of a long tradition of Kantian criticism", a tradition which "dispenses with the contrast between the transcendental ideality of the world we know and the reality of things as they are in themselves" (p.vii f.).  It is beyond the scope of this dissertation to consider in detail Strawson's positive views regarding Kant's work as we are concerned specifically with certain of his negative theses treating of transcendental idealism.  However, it is important to make the point that his positive views are not universally accepted either.  It is not the case that his critics believe him to be correct on all issues but transcendental idealism; it is held, rather, that he has, in placing so much emphasis on the transcendental deduction and transcendental arguments as a means to "search for a minimal objective framework in our experience" (Ameriks, p.6), lost or given up most of the philosophical advantages to be gained from the study of Kant's text.  Thus, Walker (perhaps the most extreme proponent of this view) believes that the interpretative tradition represented by Strawson,

has been misguided in its underestimate of transcendental idealism and equally misguided in its overestimate of what can be achieved without it. Transcendental idealism will not solve every problem, and is not without difficulties of its own, but the alternative of relying on transcendental arguments turns out to be much more disappointing than its proponents expect.... (p.viii)

Walker's argument is that whilst Strawson believes that transcendental arguments can establish conclusions about what the world must be like and that Kant's assigning of the limiting features of experience to our "cognitive constitution" (Strawson, p.15) constitutes an "unwarranted extra step" (Walker,p.122), it is in fact Strawson himself who is guilty of having taken such a step.  For Walker, "To say we must apply the concept of an object in our experience is to say we must think there are objects; but it would take a further move to show that there actually are" (p.122).  This vexed question of the status of transcendental arguments also leads Ameriks to conclude that "although this approach has been very popular, it can no longer be said to be intrinsically promising" and furthermore that "its connection with Kant's own procedure in the Critique is quite questionable" (p.6).

 

  Allison echoes Walker's assessment of the importance of Strawson, seeing 'The Bounds of Sense' as a major factor in the continued acceptance of what he terms the "standard picture" (p.3).  For Allison, this view involves holding that :

Kant's transcendental idealism is a metaphysical theory that affirms the unknowability of the "real" (things in themselves) and relegates knowledge to the purely subjective realm of representations (appearances).  It thus combines a phenomenalistic account of what is actually experienced by the mind, and therefore knowable, with the postulation of an additional set of entities which, in terms of the very theory, are unknowable.  (p.3f.)

This "standard picture" presented by Allison is indeed very close to the interpretation put forward by Strawson as will be seen in what follows.  This type of two-pronged attack on transcendental idealism, which will be characterized as charges of 'phenomenalism' and 'noumenalism' respectively, comprise the heart of Strawson's objections.  These two elements will be considered in turn after a brief overview of Strawson's approach to the Critique as a whole.  Particular attention will be given to the charge of noumenalism, especially as it bears on the self in itself, in line with the theme of "sujectivity".  Other aspects of Strawson's attack will be treated as secondary and only the briefest outline of a response will be attempted.

 

Strawson's Critique

 

  T.E. Wilkerson, in his book which often seems to to be more of a sympathetic exposition of Strawson's views than it is an independent commentary on Kant's work writes:

[Kant] expresses his problem in the form , How are synthetic a priori judgements possible ? [....] But I am going to suggest a slightly different way of approaching the 'Critique of Pure Reason' which is much clearer and much more helpful when one is actually confronted with the text.  It is the approach originally developed with considerable philosophical profit in P.F. Strawson's 'Bounds of Sense'.  I am going to suppose that instead of asking , How are synthetic a priori propositions possible ?, Kant is really asking, What are the necessary conditions of a possible experience ? (p.13)

A key element in the reasoning behind such a re-working of Kant's enterprise is that the new formulation supposedly avoids the need to invoke the active transcendental self (as an explanation of how such knowledge is possible) and indeed the whole edifice of transcendental idealism.

 

  Strawson wishes to divide the Critique into its "two faces" because he holds transcendental idealism to be fundamentally incoherent.  He has "tried to show how certain great parts of the structure can be held apart from each other, while showing also how within the system itself, they are conceived of as related" (p.11).  The reasons for such a "holding apart" are as follows :

In two ways [...Kant...] draws the bounds of sense, and in a third traverses them.  He argues, on the one hand, that a certain minimum structure is essential to any conception of experience which we can make truly intelligible to ourselves; on the other, that the attempt to extend beyond the limits of experience the use of structural concepts, or of any other concepts, leads only to claims empty of meaning [....] But Kant's arguments for these limiting conclusions are developed within the framework of a set of doctrines which themselves appear to violate his own critical principles.  He seeks to draw the bounds of sense from a point outside them, a point which, if they are rightly drawn, cannot exist. (p.11f.)

 

  For Strawson, Kant's drawing of the bounds of sense or investigation of the limits of the conceivable contains much that is of value.  Those parts of the text which form the essential elements of this investigation provide a powerful tool for establishing answers to philosophical problems once a certain amount of reconstructive work is applied to the text.  The scepticism of radical empiricism is challenged and much of the unbridled metaphysical speculation of the rationalists is ruled out.  However when it comes to Kant's attempts to "investigate the pure understanding itself, its possibility and the cognitive faculties upon which it rests", that is, his enquiry in its "subjective aspect" (Axvi), Strawson's patience quickly runs out.  He thinks that this subjective enquiry, which results in transcendental idealism with its flawed doctrines of phenomena and noumena leading to the idea of "the ultimate subjectivity of the natural world" (p.41), is based on a "misleading" or "strained" analogy.  Kant is held to have ignored the differences between his objective investigation (the key aspect of which is the transcendental deduction) which is philosophical and the subjective (which is properly a matter for empirical science) because he was misled by the analogy he drew between the two.  For Strawson this led to Kant's key mistake, i.e.; "Wherever he found limiting or necessary general features of experience, he declared their source to lie in our own cognitive constitution" (p.15).  Strawson holds that rather than explaining the possibility of knowledge, such doctrines mask the insights to be found in Kant's work.  Thus to "hold apart" the two sides of the Critique is to render Kant a service.

 

  The task then is to assess the strength of Strawson's attack on those doctrines which he wished to strip away from the uncontaminated results of transcendental arguments.  One must first consider how Strawson characterizes the doctrines of transcendental idealism and then whether or not his interpretations are fair to the text or the only possible reading.  On some points it will be argued that there are alternative interpretations available which should be cosidered as of least equal validity whereas on other points an attempt will be made to show that his objections do not necessarily constitute a fatal blow against transcendental idealism.

 

  H.E. Matthews summarizes Strawson's position, claiming that, "for Strawson transcendental idealism equals phenomenalism plus noumenalism" (p.133), echoing Allison's charaterization of the "standard picture".  Whilst Strawson does not explicitly put it in these terms, his eight-fold division of the doctrines (pp.236-9) would seem to support such a characterization.  Elsewhere he talks of "mixed idealism" (p.197) and "the phenomenalistic idealism which the transcendental variety seems to include" (p.257).  Also the Strawson-influenced Wilkerson argues that transcendental idealism consists of "two quite distinct doctrines, phenomenalism and noumenalism" (p.181f.).  Thus we are faced with the questions, 'Is Kant a phenomenalist ?' and 'is he a noumenalist ?'  It is proposed to deal with these two key questions in turn in the belief that, as they address that which constitutes the essence of his attack, any conclusion different from Strawson's own cannot but call into question the power of that assault.

 

Kant as Phenomenalist

 

  Firstly then the question of Kant as phenomenalist.  As Strawson notes, Kant wished to make a sharp distinction between transcendental idealism and other forms of idealism.  However, he argues, "when we see how Kant supports this claim [....] we must view it with scepticism" (p.21) for "Kant as transcendental idealist, is closer to Berkeley than he acknowledges" (p.22).  Such claims are not new; as M.R. Ayers notes, "Ever since its first publication critics of Kant's 'Critique of Pure Reason' have been struck by certain strong formal resemblances between transcendental idealism and Berkeley's immaterialism" (p.51).  Indeed such claims were so widely made on the appearance of the first edition that the second edition contained new material specifically written to remove the grounds for such a comparison.  An objection can be raised against all such comparisons, for as G. Bird argues, "There is, of course, here a serious problem of interpretation [....] for just as Kant's views are not entirely determinate, independent of their interpretation, so the same is notoriously true of Berkeley as well.  But to suggest that within the range of views ascribable to Berkeley some are close to views within the range ascribable to Kant is to say virtually nothing" (p.84, footnote 18).  However, it is no doubt a little unfair to complain that Strawson fails to give a full interpretation of Berkeley's views in a book on Kant.  Bird's point does however show that Strawson's frequent use of this comparison as a polemical weapon in his struggle to label Kant as a phenomenalist is scarcely enlightening.  Thus in the following discussion of Kant as phenomenalist no attempt will be made to compare the text of the Critique to the work of Berkeley.

 

  Strawson claims to find much support in Kant's text for his assertion that transcendental idealism is in part made up of "a relatively familiar kind of phenomenalistic idealism" (p.240).  He writes:

In the assertions of the Aesthetic, in the arguments of the Deduction and the Analogies, in the solutions to the problems offered in the Dialectic, we find repeatedly the refrain that bodies in space, being appearances only, have no existence distinct from our representations or perceptions, that they are but a species of the latter, that apart from our perceptions, they are nothing at all. (p.257)

The passages wherein Strawson finds "strikingly bold affirmations" (p.258) of his thesis is in the discussion of the Fourth Paralogism.  The point of Kant's argument here is to deny the Cartesian thesis that we must infer the existence of the external world.  Kant is unhappy with such a claim because "the inference from a given effect to a determinate cause is always uncertain, since the effect may be due to more than one cause" (A368).  Kant believes that transcendental idealism "removes all difficulty in the way of accepting the existence of matter on the unaided testimony of our mere self-consciousness" (A370).  The difficulty is removed by denying the need for inference.  The only difference between the representation of self as thinking subject (which Descartes accepts) and representations which "mark extended beings" (A371) is that the former belong only to inner sense whereas the latter also belong to outer sense.  Both are immediate objects of perception thus there is no need for inference at all.  As Kant writes, "in both cases alike the objects are nothing but representations, the immediate perception (consciousness) of which is at the same time a sufficient proof of their reality" (A371).  Scepticism regarding the external world is countered because, "these external things, namely matter, are in all their configurations and alterations, nothing but mere appearances, that is, representations in us" (A371-2).

 

  It cannot be denied that such passages as this lend themselves to Strawson's accusation of phenomenalism as Allison (p.31) and Matthews (p.135), both defenders of transcendental idealism, admit.  However, it is not the case that this is the only possible interpretation of such talk.  As is so often the case, an examination of other parts of Kant's text can lead to a very different picture to that which is gleaned from reading talk of "in us" out of its wider context.  Allison suggests that a non-phenomenalist reading of Kant's position is the result of an examination of his remarks concerning the existence of unperceived entities and events (pp.31-34).  Citing the example of Kant's consideration of the possibility of the moon being inhabited (A493-4/B522-3), he notes that Kant "like both Berkeley and the contemporary phenomenalist, translates first-order statements about unperceived entities or events into second-order statements about the possible perceptions thereof" (p.32).  However, for Allison, "this superficial resemblance really masks the distinctive feature of the Kantian analysis : the role given to a priori laws or principles" (ibid.).

 

  Allison further elucidates his point by means of a consideration of Kant's analysis of 'actuality'.  Again he admits that the definition of the 'actual' as "that which is bound up with the material conditions of experience, that is, with sensation" (A218/B266), seemingly invites a phenomenalistic reading.  However, Kant continues :

The postulate bearing on the knowledge of things as 'actual' does not, indeed, demand immediate perception (and, therefore, sensation of which we are conscious) of the object whose existence is to be known.  What we do, however, require is the connection of the object with some actual perception, in accordance with the analogies of experience, which define all real connection in an experience in general. (A225/B272)

As Allison notes, the point of this passage is that Kant does hold that an 'actual' event or entity must be an object of possible perception but this is not a criterion of the 'actual' but rather a consequence of the necessary application of the "analogies of experience" whereas in phenomenalism the possibility is itself the criterion for 'actuality'.  For Kant, "the appeal to perception or sensation here functions merely as the point of departure, which gives empirical content to the claim of actuality.  The claim itself is not about any "subjective experiences"" (Allison, p.33).

 

  Whereas Allison produces arguments specifically challenging the charge of phenomenalism, Matthews uses what is essentially the same approach to both strands of Strawson's attack, i.e. both phenomenalism and noumenalism.  R.B. Pippin notes that the type of approach adopted by Matthews is often called the "two aspect" view and characterizes it as a "project [which] attempts to interpret the distinction between appearances and things in themselves as a distinction between two ways of considering objects - "as" they appear, subject to human conditions for the possibility of experience, and "as" they are in themselves, considered hypothetically apart from these conditions - and so not between two types of objects" (p.366).  Allison also holds a version of this view, to be considered below in the section on noumenalism.  As Matthews presents this view, the point is that Kant is not making an ontological point but rather "an epistemological point about the limits of human knowledge" (p.136).

 

  According to Matthews, such an understanding of what Kant is doing leads to an interpretation of talk of "representations" being "in us" which is radically different to the phenomenalism / noumenalism hybrid which Strawson reads into such passages.  In support of his "two aspect" view, Matthews, in his discussion of Kant's views on the nature of appearances, points to the following passage from the Transcendental Aesthetic :

It is, therefore, solely from the human standpoint that we can speak of space, of extended things, etc.  If we depart from the subjective condition under which we alone can have outer intuition, namely, liability to be affected by objects, the representations of space stand for nothing whatsoever.  This predicate can be ascribed to things only in so far as they appear to us, that is, only to objects of sensibility. (A26/B42)

In this passage the reference to "the human standpoint" and being "affected by objects" does indeed seem to back a "two aspect" approach.  Objects are not denied, nor are two 'sets' of objects or two worlds posited.  Rather, Kant is holding that in order for us to have knowledge (human experience) the form must be applied by us to the matter which is in some sense 'given'.

 

  This "two aspect" approach will be examined in more detail in connection with noumena.  It is important at this point to understand why Strawson holds that "Kant fails to satisfy the conditions for a significant application of the contrast between things as they really are and things as they appear" (p.254) and by what "distortions and perversions" (p.249) such a failure arises.  Strawson argues that for any such distinction to be significantly drawn two concepts are essential, identity of reference and the notion of the corrected view (p.250).  The idea of a contrast between appearance and reality as two standpoints necessarily implies the same 'thing' is being referred to and that the 'real' is a corrected view of what 'appears' to be the case.  Whilst Strawson holds that there is "no logical compulsion" to make a distinction at all between appearance and reality, he points to philosophers such as Locke and Russell who have taken this step without becoming unintelligible.  On a view such as theirs, our perceptions are 'appearances' whilst the explanation of the cause of such phenomena can be called the 'reality'.  This is intelligible because "Things as they really are, are not removed from the spatio-temporal framework of reference.  They are simply things as science speaks of them rather than as we perceive them.  The corrected view is the view of science; it is a different view, but it is a view of the same things as our ordinary uncorrected view is a view of" (p.252).

 

  It is with regard to removal from the "spatio-temporal framework" that Strawson finds the difference between Kant and the "scientifically minded philosopher".  Whilst the latter maintains the connection to sensible experience, albeit in a less direct form, thus allowing knowledge of things as they really are (in terms of scientific description rather than perceptual acquaintance), "Kant denies the possibility of any empirical knowledge at all of those things, as they are in themselves" (p.40).  Strawson's complaint here is that by assigning even space and time to our cognitive constitution, Kant is not able to give any intelligible meaning to the idea of things in themselves "affecting" this constitution.  On Kant's account the only 'corrected' view is "non-sensible intuition" the possibility of which we are unable to comprehend.

 

  Matthews' response to the above is to claim that Kant is not using "appearances" in the sense that it is used by  those philosophers to whom Strawson compares him, in that it refers to all human experience and thus "one can hardly object [....] that he cannot give it significance in the way that one can give significance to the word as normally used" (p.146).  This response, of itself, does not of course fully resolve the problems concerning the cognitive constitution.  Any attempt at such a resolution necessitates a full consideration of those aspects of transcendental idealism which have been dubbed 'noumenalism'.  As can be seen in the discussion thus far, it is difficult, if not impossible to maintain a rigid distinction between the two charges levelled by Strawson.  Strawson seems to admit as much.  He concedes that the charge of phenomenalism does not in itself prove fatal, the main thrust of his attack being aimed at the incoherence of the notion of the thing in itself, the self in itself, their relation and how they produce phenomena.  He writes thus :

The fact that within the framework of the theory of transcendental idealism a form of reconciliation is possible between the thesis that we are aware of bodies in space as objects distinct from our perceptions and the thesis that bodies in space have no existence apart from our perceptions has no power to restore to the theory of transcendental idealism the coherence and intelligibility it [can be...] shown to lack [on other grounds]. (p.260)

 

Kant as Noumenalist

 

  We must now consider the charge of noumenalism that Strawson raises against Kant.  For Strawson, noumena comprises the real world in what he sees as Kant's two-world view.  All reference to the "supersensible" or "things as they are in themselves" within the context of transcendental idealism involves the positing of a "sphere of supersensible reality, of things, neither spatial nor temporal, as they are in themselves" (p.236).  It is in this sphere that the phenomenal world is created by means of the quasi-causal interaction of things in themselves and the self in itself or the passive and active elements of this realm.  It is in this two-world view which Strawson recognizes at the heart of transcendental idealism that the radical incoherence of the system is best exemplified.  As Allison notes, "of all the criticisms that have been raised against Kant's philosophy, the most persistent is that he has no right to affirm the existence of things in themselves, noumena, or a transcendental object, much less to talk about such things as somehow "affecting" the mind" (p.237).  Such indeed is Strawson's position.  How can Kant who has accomplished so much against the ungrounded metaphysical speculation of his rationalist predecessors fall so far foul of his own critical principles as to hold that "reality is supersensible and that we can have no knowledge of it" (p.38).

 

  But a question must be raised as to whether Strawson is in fact correct in claiming that Kant posits the existence of a supersensible realm which is ontologically distinct from the world of appearances thus engendering huge problems concerning interaction as well as opening himself to the obvious retort that if knowledge requires both concepts and intuitions then how could we know anything about such a realm, even that it exists ? 

 

  This question will be examined as it relates to the issue of the self in itself, or the active self of transcendental idealism, in line with the theme of "subjectivity".  The key part of Strawson's text to be considered here is the section, 'The Thing-In-Itself and Appearances in Inner Sense' (pp.247-9).  As K. Ameriks notes, these aspects of Kant's work are of particular interest (and have encountered much resistance),

for (as Kant himself noted) although there are many who would grant that the world may be really quite other than we think of it as being, the reason for granting this is often quite simply the idea that, in contrast, one's own self must be what it appears to be.  At the very least, Kant forces us to see that this resistance rests on a questionable doctrine, and that self-knowledge may well be parasitic on, and so suffer the same fate as, knowledge of the world at large. (p.9)

 

  Ameriks, at least in part, attributes Kant's moves in this direction to a commitment to the traditional rationalist search for a stable self underlying the transient empirical one and a desire to recast this commitment "into a respectable form" (p.9).  Strawson would agree with Ameriks to the extent that Kant is influenced by his rationalist predecessors but rather than finding anything even faintly respectable in Kant's doctrines, finds rather the most "incautious" statements of noumenalism arising just at those points where Kant is most concerned with morality and freedom and thus the self.  Despite attempts to avoid speaking of noumena as objects elsewhere, it is in the context of such issues that he shows his noumenalist hand, as it were, and provides us with the most "decisive reasons for thinking that [...weaker readings of the doctrines of transcendental idealism...] would altogether fail to answer to Kant's intentions" (p.22).  Strawson holds that when writing on the self Kant is concerned "to curb the pretensions of sensibility to be co-extensive with the real [...because...] the proof of our necessary ignorance of the supersensible safeguards the interests of morality and religion by securing the supersensible realm from our scepticism as well as from our knowledge" (p.22).  However whilst the reconciliation of Newton and God or the claim to have denied knowledge "in order to make room for faith" (Bxxx) may have been one of Kant's proudest claims, he does not (as Strawson notes, p.241) actually use such considerations as a premise from which to argue for the doctrines of transcendental idealism.  It is rather that they lead him on to his most glaring "lapses" (as Wilkerson characterizes them, p.191).

 

  These "lapses" occur because, Strawson holds, "it is manifestly, of importance to him to ensure that there is a point of connexion, in the way of identity, between the supersensible world and the world of human beings" (p.247).  Without such a connexion it would be of no relevance to us that there existed a supersensible realm wherein freedom and thus the possibility of morality held sway.  Furthermore without this link between the self in itself as seat of the forms of both sensibility and understanding and our empirical selves "it would be impossible to assemble, let alone to work, that crude model of imposed necessities available [....] to our non-empirical knowledge" (p.247).  Strawson identifies Kant's answer to the puzzle of the connexion in the following passage from the Antinomies :

Man, however, who knows all the rest of nature through the senses, knows himself also through pure apperception; and this, indeed, in acts and inner determinations which he cannot regard as impressions of the senses.  He is thus to himself, on the one hand phenomenon, and on the other hand, in respect of certain faculties which cannot be ascribed to sensibility, a purely intelligible object.  We entitle these faculties understanding and reason. (A546-7/B574-5)

 

  Strawson interprets this passage as asserting that the connexion is made between the individual as natural being and as supersensible being by means of his/her consciousness of the "possession and exercise of the power of thought, of the faculties of understanding and reason" (p.248).  He objects to such an attempt at forging the connexion on the grounds that, on Kantian principles, any such experience must occur in time and be an experience of a definite, temporal conscious process.  Hence, for Strawson, there can be no way in which this supposed clarification of the connexion can concern anything which is supersensible, i.e. a self in itself outside of a temporal framework; thus it cannot do the work necessary for making the link so vital to Kant's enterprise.  Furthermore, "Kant faces these difficulties again and again in more cautious passages in the Aesthetic, in the Deduction, in the Paralogisms." (p.248).

 

  It is worth considering some of these other "more cautious passages", for reasons which will become apparent.  Unfortunately, Strawson, at this key point in his attack on the notion of a transcendental self, neglects to give precise references; this being perhaps symptomatic of his general disdain for such matters and a feeling that he has already sufficiently undermined the doctrine's claim to intelligibility in his comments on the passage quoted above.  An attempt has been made to be fair to Strawson in the selection of the following quotes, all of which, initially at least, appear to lend support to his views, whilst they may not be, in every case, the precise passage he intended (the quote from B157 is specifically referenced by Strawson).  Thus in the Aesthetic we find :

Everything that is represented through a sense is so far always appearance, and consequently we must either refuse to admit that there is an inner sense, or we must recognise that the subject, which is the object of the sense, can be represented through it only as appearance, not as that subject would judge of itself if its intuition were self-activity only, that is, were intellectual. (B68)

In the Deduction we have :

"...in the transcendental synthesis of the manifold of representations in general, and therefore in the synthetic original unity of apperception, I am conscious of myself, not as I appear to myself, nor as I am in myself, but only that I am.  This representation is a thought, not an intuition." (B157).

Also :

I have no knowledge of myself as I am but merely as I appear to myself.  The consciousness of self is thus very far from being a knowledge of the self... (B158)

Finally, in the Paralogisms, we find :

[for]...the thinking self [....] to know itself as noumenon [....] is impossible, since the empirical intuition is sensible and yields only data of appearances, which furnish nothing to the object of pure consciousness for the knowledge of its separate existence, but can serve only for the obtaining of experience. (B430)

This latter is, however, then seemingly contradicted by the following :

And we should also become aware that in the consciousness of our existence there is contained a something a priori, which can serve to determine our existence [....] as being related, in respect of a certain inner faculty, to a non-sensible intelligible world. (B431-2)

 

  According to Strawson, none of these passages make the "identity which has to be explained - the identity of the empirically self-conscious subject and the real or supersensible subject - [....] a whit more intelligible." (p.248f.).  Any attempt to make good the connexion that is needed must traverse "the limits of intelligibility" (p.249) or the "bounds of sense" for, as the self-consciousness in question must be both experience of and experience for a temporal self, all reference to a self as it (supersensibly) is in itself "drops out as superfluous and unjustified" (ibid.).  Thus, he concludes, "What has the non-history of the transcendental subject to do with us ?" (ibid.).

 

  Furthermore, the reference to "synthesis" at B157 cannot but cloud the issue further on a Strawsonian account.  The doctrine of synthesis is amongst the worst excesses of the subjective aspect of Kant's enquiry or, in that it "rests firmly on the distinction of faculties" (p.97), represents the greatest extravagence of his psychological idiom so often conflated with the logical investigations of the Critique.  The doctrine of synthesis comprises the details of the workings of the self in itself, the underlying mechanism of the transcendental unity of apperception.  As such it represents Kant squaring up to the question laid out in the preface at Axvii - "how is the faculty of thought itself possible ?" and lies at the heart of his Copernican revolution, putting the flesh on the bones of the supposition that "objects must conform to our knowledge" (Bxvi).  For Strawson, Kant's "transcendental subjectivism, the theory of the mind making nature" (p.22) can only become more incoherent as detail is added to the "disastrous model" (p.21).  Given his allegation of unintelligibility against the very notion of a self in itself, it is unsuprising that he should dismiss the detail as "mysterious bits of non-temporal machinery" (Matthews' characterization of Strawson's position, p.146), the explication of which is to be by-passed because "...it is useless to puzzle over the status of these propositions..." (p.97).

 

  It is at this point, however, that we must question Strawson's interpretation of the above passages (especially that from the Antinomies), which he believes to constitute a damning indictment of Kant's notion of a self in itself in that they show him embroiled in a confusion and incoherence which put him in conflict with his own critical principles.  Initially, it might be argued that one could put the matter even more strongly than Strawson himself does.  One might hold, for example, that the "incautious" talk (in the Antinomies passage) of man being to himself "a purely intelligible object" not only falls into a contradiction as regards Kant's principle of significance (which, however, it is not clear that Kant held, as was noted in the introduction) but that it also actually contradicts his more "cautious" statements which try to avoid talking of the noumenal self as an object.  Thus, on this view, one could argue that the other passages cited are not in fact more cautious versions of the same position but are in fact entirely inconsistent with it (perhaps supporting the 'patchwork' theory, proposed by some critics, which sees such difficulties as arising out of the fact that the Critique was put together from diverse fragments composed at different times without sufficient editing).  Thus the other passages cited above, taken together, recognise the impossibility of intellectual intuition and the extract from B158 in particular agrees with the anti-Cartesian conclusions of the Paralogisms in a way that the "incautious" statement does not.  This does not mean, however, that the passages from the Aesthetic, Deduction and Paralogisms are without difficulties of their own, the seeming contradiction between the two excerpts from the Paralogisms being perhaps the most problematic.  Thus, to summarize, on a Strawsonian reading of the Antinomies passage, the inconsistency between the various statements and hence the incoherence of each is greater even than Strawson holds to be the case.

 

  But might not this very inconsistency point to another possible conclusion - that Strawson's reading of the "incautious" Antinomies passage is incorrect ?  A line of interpretation that brings all the above passages into closer agreement is indeed possible and it is one that radically challenges the accusation of incoherence by questioning the basic tenet of Strawson's case for Kant being a noumenalist, i.e. the two world view.  A clue to an altogether different interpretation is to be found in the motivation for the "lapses" which both Strawson and Wilkerson identify as lying behind the Antinomies passage in particular and noumenalism as regards the self in general - "the supposed interests of morality" (Strawson, p.248).  The point here is that the very fact that Kant is concerned at such points with morality means that he is not concerned with knowledge claims at all but with presuppositions of practical reason.  Kant would in fact agree that no connexion could be made between the two worlds envisioned by Strawson and that we could have no knowledge of a supersensible world; but he has no need to make the link that Strawson holds to be so vital as he has not posited any such world.

 

  Such passages as that from the Antinomies can in fact be read from the perspective of the "two aspect" view with interesting results.  Those passages where Kant does seemingly invoke a noumenal self can be seen as a special case as regards the "two aspect" or "standpoint" (cf. A26/B42, quoted above, p.11)view.  As Matthews puts it,

We can draw a contrast between two different human standpoints : the standpoint of experience and the standpoint of action [....] This contrast is made by Kant in the form of a distinction between the standpoints of theoretical and practical reason. (p.138)

Theoretical reason is concerned with statements which make knowledge claims whereas practical reason is concerned with "statements which express presuppositions of our activity as desiring or willing beings" (ibid.).  For Matthews, these latter statements are to be seen thus :

[They] have content, [but] not in the sense that they embody knowledge about objects [...and furthermore] the system of these presuppositions may be called a 'supersensible world' or an 'intelligible world', not in the sense that it consists of objects which can only be known about by non-sensory or intellectual intuition, but in the sense that its 'objects' are not objects of knowledge at all, but 'objectively real' presuppositions of activity. (p.139)

 

  It is interesting to consider how the passages cited at p.16f. might be read in the light of this distinction made by Matthews.  First the passage from the Antinomies.  Backed by the "standpoint" view we are able to read the reference to "a purely intelligible object" as being a reference to that which is posited when seeking to understand oneself as an active being; it is not a claim to know a noumenal self but rather consists in an unpacking of a necessary presupposition of activity.  Furthermore, one can find backing for applying the "standpoint" view to this passage in other parts Kant's text for, in a passage following closely on the one in question (at A550/B578), he quite clearly himself invokes the distinction between "speculative reason" and "reason in its practical bearing".

 

  Thus we seem to be able to bring this most "incautious" statement into line with those from the Aesthetic and the Deduction which clearly deny any direct intuition of a noumenal self.  However, one might still ask of the Deduction passage B157 (specifically cited by Strawson as problematic), what does it mean to say that "this representation is a thought" ?  Does this not still constitute a claim to knowledge ?  To answer this objection, one might consider an interpretation of the "noumenal self" put forward by Allison.  He begins by noting that "the characterization of the subject of apperception as a "transcendental subject = x" [A346/B404] is not intended to assign the act of thinking to some inaccessible noumenal entity, which is nonetheless to be identified with one's "real" self" (p.290).  Such a characterization, argues Allison, is made solely to undermine the pretensions of rational psychology to any more informative answer to the question of the identity of the I which thinks.  Armed with this point made by Allison we can interpret "I am conscious of myself [....] only that I am.  This representation is a thought...." (B157) as meaning that "reflection yields only the bare thought of a subject that must be presupposed as a condition of thinking" (Allison, p.290).

 

  Thus here again we come up against the concept of a "presupposition".  But what does it mean in this context, as we are obviously not here concerned with morality and thus the distinction between theoretical and practical reason ?  Allison makes this clear by drawing an interesting parallel with Wittgenstein's Tractatus.  For Wittgenstein, "The subject does not belong to the world : rather, it is a limit of the world" (TLP 5.632) and again, "The philosophical self is not the human being, not the human body, or the human soul, with which psychology deals, but rather the metaphysical subject, the limit of the world - not a part of it" (TLP 5.641).  Similarly, Kant holds that "I cannot know as an object that which I must presuppose in order to know any object" (A402) and further that "a transcendental subject [....] is known only through the thoughts which are its predicates, and of it, apart from them, we cannot have any concept whatsoever, but can only revolve in a perpetual circle, since any judgement upon it has always already made use of its representation" (A346/B404).  Thus one cannot know the self in itself and, as these latter quotes make plain, Kant was quite clear that this was impossible, for he realised of the transcendental subject that it (as Allison puts it) "must be thought of as already on the scene, doing the conceptualizing" (p.292).  Thus, contra Strawson, this subject is not, and cannot be, an object but is rather a limit, a necessarily presupposed ground to the very possibility of representation.

 

  Finally, to deal with the seeming contradiction between the two passages cited from the Paralogisms (from B430-2, see p.17) we need only return to the theoretical / practical distinction made by Matthews and link it to Allison's comments regarding Kant's attack on the pretensions of rational psychology.  Bearing these lessons in mind, a construction most unlike Strawson's can be put on the latter passage's reference to "being related [....] to a non-sensible intelligible world" (B431).  As the passage immediately following the one cited makes plain, it is again the rational psychologists that are being derided and the only sense in which we might be conceived of as being "related" to any noumenal realm is from the viewpoint of "the practical employment [of reason]" (ibid.).  A further criticism of Strawson's position can be made by means of a consideration of the penultimate sentence of this section (and the Paralogisms as a whole).  Kant writes thus : "These observations are designed merely to prevent a misunderstanding to which the doctrine of our self-intuition, as appearance, is particularly liable" (B432).  This warning could have been specifically aimed at Strawson for, as Ameriks notes, "Strawson speaks as if for Kant the noumenal subject is alone real, and what is phenomenal is simply false" (p.283).  But, he continues, Kant was well aware of such objections and "clearly emphasises that by saying the temporality of experience is wholly phenomenal ('only appearance'), he doesn't mean to say that it only appears to be the case that we have experience, or it only appears that this experience has a temporal nature (B69)" (ibid.).  It is thus again made clear that it can be held on good grounds that Strawson is quite simply wrong to hold that for Kant, "reality is supersensible" (Strawson, p.38).

 

  However, to return to the main thrust of the defence of the Kantian transcendental self against Strawson's charge of noumenalism that has been put forward here, i.e. the "two aspect" view; we have seen how it performs this specific task and must now give it a general characterization.  Matthews' version of the "two aspect" view (though he does not refer to it as such) consists in holding that Kant "in distinguishing 'appearances' from 'things in themselves', [...] is contrasting, not two types of thing, but two ways of considering the same things" (p.137), a formulation that closely echoes Pippin's characterization of this type of view.  Matthews further holds that on such a view one may clearly maintain that "Kant nowhere asserts that there are noumena in [the positive] sense" (p.138), i.e. that he posits a seperate realm of things in themselves.  Laying great emphasis on Kant's talk of "the human standpoint" (A26/B42), Matthews concludes that rather than claiming knowledge of the supersensible (as Strawson claims), Kant is interested merely in the concept of such a world in order to draw attention to the limits of our knowledge - "The point of the Copernican revolution is to remind philosophers that they are not Gods" (p.144).

 

  Allison gives a much more fully worked out version of the "two aspect" view which can only be outlined here.  The key concept in Allison's approach is the "epistemic condition" which, he argues, "allows us to make good sense of the transcendental distinction between things as they appear and things as they are in themselves, and of Kant's "Copernican" assumption that objects "conform to our knowledge"" (p.330).  As E. Forster summarises Allison's position, he makes a distinction between how the ideal / real duality is applied at the empirical and at the transcendental level.  In the former case ideal means subjective and real means inter-subjective whereas "at the transcendental level, by contrast, 'ideal' is said to refer to universal and necessary a priori conditions of human knowledge, to what Allison terms "epistemic conditions"" (p.734).  At this level something is ideal when considered via these conditions and real if considered independently of them.  As Allison himself puts it :

the task of a transcendental justification of the concept of the thing in itself (and its associated concepts [including the self in itself]) is to explain the possibility and significance of considering "as they are in themselves" the same objects which we can know only as they appear; it is not, as is frequently assumed, to license the appeal to a set of unknown entities distinct from appearances.  (p.239)

Allison further argues that in talking of a thing as it appears or as it is in itself, "the relevant terms function adverbially to characterize how we consider things in transcendental reflection, not substantively to characterize what it is that is being considered or reflected upon" (p.241).  Such then is the "two aspect" view which we have seen applied to the notion of the self in itself.

 

Conclusion

 

  The conclusion which can be drawn from the above is that we need not be as dismissive of transcendental idealism as Strawson would have us be.  The main reason for this view is that his characterization of Kant's position as amounting to a two-world view, composed of an incoherent hybrid of phenomenalism and noumenalism is not the only possible interpretation and is indeed highly questionable.  The major emphasis here has been on the self in itself as it occurs in transcendental idealism and much attention has been given to the "two aspect" interpretative approach which, as has hopefully been shown, can be applied to such issues with some profit.  The key point which it is believed has been established herein is that the transcendental self is by no means as unintelligible or incoherent a notion as Strawson holds it to be.  However, this emphasis has of course meant that other aspects of transcendental idealism have been ignored, both Strawson's objections and defences of such doctrines by a number of critics.  This being the case, the above cannot be claimed to be a full or adequate defence against Strawson's assault, although it does attempt to rock the major pillars of that structure.

 

  Two key areas that it was not possible to cover here in any depth are the question of things in themselves or noumena in general (i.e. other than the self in itself) and the details of transcendental psychology (the faculties, synthesis, etc.). Strawson's assault on the former might again be seriously impacted by an application of the "two aspect" view (as well as by a consideration of papers by L. Chipman and J. Srzednicki) and the latter could be approached in terms of a position laid out in P. Kitcher's book on the subject (although the position therein is in a complex and not entirely sympathetic relation to the doctrines of transcendental idealism). 

 

  Neither Strawson's antagonism towards the kind of "weakened" (p.22) or "anodyne" (p.38) interpretations he considers possible or Wilkerson's defence of him against Matthews (p.185f.) constitute a strong case against the "two aspect" approach because they do not seriously challenge the view that such interpretations are not at least of equal validity as their own.  Thus, the conclusion drawn is that we are by no means forced into following Strawson's 'austere' reading of the Critique.

 

Bibliography

 

ALLISON, H.E. (1983); Kant's Transcendental Idealism: an Interpretation and Defense; Yale University Press

 

AMERIKS, K. (1982); Kant's Theory of Mind; Clarendon Press

 

AYER, A.J. (1946); Language, Truth and Logic (second edition); Penguin Books Ltd.

 

AYERS, M.R. (1982); 'Berkeley's immaterialism and Kant's transcendental idealism' in Vesey, G. (Ed.) Idealism Past and Present (Royal Institute of Philosophy Lecture Series:13) pp51-69; Cambridge University Press

 

BIRD, G. (1982); 'Kant's transcendental idealism' in Vesey, G. (Ed.) Idealism Past and Present (Royal Institute of Philosophy Lecture Series:13) pp71-92;  Cambridge University Press

             

CHIPMAN, L. (1972); 'Things in themselves' Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 33 pp489-502

 

DAVIES, K. (1982); 'The concept of experience and Strawson's transcendental deduction' Analysis 42 pp16-19

 

FORSTER, E. (1985); Review of Allison, H.E. (as above) The Journal of Philosophy 82 pp734-738

 

KANT, I. (1781 and 1787); Kritik der reinen Vernunft tr. N. Kemp Smith as Critique of Pure Reason;  Macmillan (1929)

 

KITCHER, P. (1990); Kant's Transcendental Psychology; Oxford University Press

 

MATTHEWS, H.E.(1969); 'Strawson on transcendental idealism' Philosophical Quarterly 19 Reprinted in Walker, R.C.S. (Ed.) Kant on Pure Reason pp132-149;  Oxford University Press

 

PIPPIN, R.B. (1986); Review of Allison, H.E. (as above) Kantstudien 77 pp365-371

 

SOLOMON, R.C. (1988); Continental Philosophy Since 1750; Oxford University Press

 

SRZEDNICKI, J. (1984); 'On Strawson's criticism of Kant's "transcendental idealism"' Kantstudien 75 pp94-103

 

STRAWSON, P.F. (1966); The Bounds of Sense; Methuen

 

WALKER, R.C.S. (1978); Kant; Routledge and Kegan Paul

 

WILKERSON, T.E. (1976); Kant's Critique of Pure Reason; Clarendon Press

 

WITTGENSTEIN, L. (1922); Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus  tr. D.F. Pears & B.F. McGuiness (1961); Routledge and Kegan Paul

 

© 1993